Sunday, March 16, 2014

Some enlightenment on Giordano Bruno

I hear that the relaunched Cosmos TV series has included a little hagiography of Giordano Bruno as a martyr to Copernican science, and I sigh. If I was a sensible chap, I would simply accept this myth is never now going to be squashed, because it seems to be too important to many people as a means of “showing” how the Roman Church was determined to stamp out the kind of independent and anti-dogmatic thought that supposedly gave rise to modern science. In short, Bruno fills the same martyr’s role here as early Christians needed to sustain their own faith.

But I am not a sensible chap, because I persist with this fantasy that one day everyone will be persuaded to go back and look at the history and see that this portrayal of Bruno is a (relatively) modern invention – an aspect of the nineteenth-century Draper-White narrative that pitched science in head-on combat with the Church. I am foolish enough to imagine that what I wrote in my book Curiosity is actually going to be read and heeded:
“The Neapolitan friar Giordano Bruno had an arrogant and argumentative nature that was bound to get him into serious trouble eventually, although if he had not happened to promote Copernican cosmology it is doubtful that he would command any greater fame today than the many other intellectual vagabonds who wandered Europe during the Counter-Reformation. It seems a vain hope that Bruno should ever cease to be the ‘martyr to science’ that modern times have made of him; maybe we must resign ourselves to the words spoken by Brecht’s Galileo: ‘Unhappy the land where heroes are needed.’
The fact is that Bruno’s Copernicanism is not mentioned in the charges levelled against him by the Inquisition in 1576, nor the denunciation of 1592 that led to his imprisonment and lengthy trial. Of the heretical accusations that condemned him to be burnt at the stake in 1600, only two are still recorded, which relate to obscure theological matters. He held many opinions of which the Church disapproved deeply, on such delicate matters as the Incarnation and the Trinity, not to mention having a long history of associating with disreputable types. Bruno’s death stains the Church’s record of tolerance for free thought, but says little about its attitude to science. There is nothing in Bruno’s espousal of a world soul, or his long discourses on demons and other spiritual beings, or his unconventional system of the elements, that makes him so very unusual for his times – but nothing either that qualifies him for canonization in the scientific pantheon.”

But then – praise be! – I see that others have done the job already, and better than I could. Corey Powell at Discover magazine has set the record straight on Bruno, and attacking this old Whig view of science history. Meg Rosenburg has posted a nice piece on Bruno too. And best of all, Rebekah Higgitt has written a masterful article in her Guardian blog about why this kind of appropriation of history to serve our modern agenda is invariably false and damaging to the historical record. As she puts it, “Historical figures who lived in a very different world, very differently understood, cannot be turned into heroes who perfectly represent our values and concerns without doing serious damage to the evidence.” And this is really the point, for I’m tired and, I fear, a little cross at scientists who seem to think that being scrupulous with the evidence only applies to science and not to something as wishy-washy as the humanities. So hurrah to all three of you!

And I couldn’t help but be struck by how, at the same time, we have Brendan O’Neil (who I can’t say I always agree with) taking Richard Dawkins to task by pointing out how the Enlightenment was not, as many alleged champions of “Enlightenment values” like to insist today, about attacking religion, but rather about demanding religious tolerance and the freedom to worship as one pleases. But Brendan doesn’t take this point far enough. For the one thing Enlightenment heroes like Voltaire and Rousseau could not abide was atheism. The Enlightenment is as abused an historical notion as Bruno’s “martyrdom” is – by much the same people and for much the same reasons. And so this motivates me to post here what I said about all this at the How The Light Gets In festival at Hay-on-Wye last summer, as part of a debate on optimism, pessimism and the legacy of the Enlightenment. Here it is.

Yes, I’m fool enough to think that this might stop some folk from banging on about “Enlightenment values.” And yes, I know that this is deeply irrational of me.

_______________________________________________________________________
“Nasty, brutish and short”: How The Light Gets In Festival, panel discussion, 1st June 2013, Hay-on-Wye.

I’ve been trying to parse the title of this discussion ever since I saw it. The blurb says “The Enlightenment taught us to believe in the optimistic values of humanism, truth and progress” – but of course the title, which sounds a much more pessimistic note, comes from Thomas Hobbes’ Leviathan, and yet Hobbes too is very much a part of the early Enlightenment. You might recall that it was Hobbes’ description of life under what he called the State of Nature: the way people live if left to their own devices, without any overarching authority to temper their instincts to exploit one another.

That scenario established the motivation for Hobbes’ attempt to deduce the most reliable way to produce a stable society. And what marks out Hobbes’ book as a key product of the Enlightenment is that he tried to develop his argument not, as previous political philosophies going back to Plato had done, according to preconceptions and prejudices, but according to strict, quasi-mathematical logic. Hobbes’ Commonwealth is a Newtonian one – or rather, to avoid being anachronistic, a Galilean one, because he attempted to generalize his reasoning from Galileo’s law of motion. This was to be a Commonwealth governed by reason. And let me remind you that what this reason led Hobbes to conclude is that the best form of government is a dictatorship.

Now of course, this sort of exercise depends crucially one what you assume about human nature from the outset. If, like Hobbes, you see people as basically selfish and acquisitive, you’re likely to end up concluding that those instincts have to be curbed by drastic measures. If you believe, like John Locke, that humankind’s violent instincts are already curbed by an intrinsic faculty of reason, then it becomes possible to imagine some kind of more liberal, communal form of self-government – although of course Locke then argued that state authority is needed to safeguard the private property that individuals accrue from their efforts.

Perhaps the most perceptive view was that of Rousseau, who argued in effect that there is no need for some inbuilt form of inhibition to prevent people acting anti-socially, because they will see that it is in their best interests to cooperate. That’s why agreeing to abide by a rule of law administered by a government is not, as in Hobbes’ case, an abdication of personal freedom, but something that people will choose freely: it is the citizen’s part of the social contract, while the government is bound by this contract to act with justice and restraint. This is, in effect, precisely the kind of emergence of cooperation that is found in modern game theory.

My point here is that reasoning about governance during the Enlightenment could lead to all kinds of conclusions, depending on your assumptions. That’s just one illustration of the fact that the Enlightenment doesn’t have anything clear to say about what people are like or how communities and nations should be run. In this way and in many others, the Enlightenment has no message for us – it was too diverse, but more importantly, it was much too immersed in the preoccupations of its times, just like any other period of history. This is one reason why I get so frustrated about the way the Enlightenment is used today as a kind of shorthand for a particular vision of humanity and society. What is most annoying of all is that that vision so often has very little connection with the Enlightenment itself, but is a modern construct. Most often, when people today talk about Enlightenment values, they are probably arguing in favour of a secular, tolerant liberal democracy in which scientific reason is afforded a special status in decision-making. I happen to be one of those people who rather likes the idea of a state of that kind, and perhaps it is for this reason that I wish others would stop trying to yoke it to the false idol of some kind of imaginary Enlightenment.

To state the bleedin’ obvious, there were no secular liberal democracies in the modern sense in eighteenth century Europe. And the heroes of the Enlightenment had no intention of introducing them. Take Voltaire, one of the icons of the Enlightenment. Voltaire had some attractive ideas about religious tolerance and separation of church and state. But he was representative of such thinkers in opposing any idea that reason should become a universal basis for thought. It was grand for the ruling classes, but far too dangerous to advocate for the lower orders, who needed to be kept in ignorance for the sake of the social order. Here’s what he said about that: “the rabble… are not worthy of being enlightened and are apt for every yoke”.

What about religion, then? Let’s first of all dispose of the idea that the Enlightenment was strongly secular. Atheism was very rare, and condemned by almost all philosophers as a danger to social stability. Rousseau calls for religious tolerance, but not for atheists, who should be banished from the state because their lack of fear of divine punishment means that they can’t be trusted to obey the laws. And even people who affirm the religious dogmas of the state but then act as if they don’t believe them should be put to death.

Voltaire has been said to be a deist, which means that he believed in a God whose existence can be deduced by reason rather than revelation, and who made the world according to rational principles. According to deists, God created the world but then left it alone – he wasn’t constantly intervening to produce miracles. It’s sometimes implied that Enlightenment deism was the first step towards secularism. But contrary to common assertions, there wasn’t any widespread deist movement in Europe at that time. And again, even ideas like this had to be confined to the better classes: the message of the church should be kept simple for the lower orders, so that they didn’t get confused. Voltaire said that complex ideas such as deism are suited only “among the well-bred, among those who wish to think.”

Well, enough Enlightenment-bashing, perhaps – but then why do we have this myth of what these people thought? Partly that comes from the source of most of our historical myths, which is Victorian scholarship. The simple idea that the Enlightenment was some great Age of Reason is now rejected by most historians, but the popular conception is still caught up with a polemical view developed in particular by two nineteenth-century Americans, John William Draper and Andrew Dickson White. Draper was a scientist who decided that scientific principles could be applied to history, and his 1862 book The History of Intellectual Development in Europe was a classic example of Whiggish history in which humankind makes a long journey out of ignorance and superstition, through an Age of Faith, into a modern Age of Reason. But where we really enter the battleground is with Draper’s 1874 book History of the Conflict between Religion and Science, in which we get the stereotypical picture of science having to struggle against the blinkered dogmatism of faith – or rather, because Draper’s main target was actually Catholicism, against the views of Rome, because Protestantism was largely exonerated. White, who founded Cornell University, gave much the same story in his 1896 book A History of the Warfare if Science with Theology in Christendom. It’s books like this that gave us the simplistic views on the persecution of Galileo that get endlessly recycled today, as well as myths such as the martyrdom of Giordano Bruno for his belief in the Copernican system. (Bruno was burnt at the stake, but not for that reason.)

The so-called “conflict thesis” of Draper and White has been discredited now, but it still forms a part of the popular view of the Enlightenment as the precursor to secular modernity and to the triumph of science and reason over religious dogma.

Bur why, if these things are so lacking in historical support, do intelligent people still invoke the Enlightenment trope today whenever they fear that irrational forces are threatening to undermine science? Well, I guess we all know that our critical standards tend to plummet when we encounter idea that confirm our preconceptions. But it’s more than this. It is one thing to argue for how we would prefer things to be, but far more effective to suggest that things were once like that, and that this wonderful state of affairs is now being undermined by ignorant and barbaric hordes. It’s the powerful image of the Golden Age, and the rhetoric of a call to arms to defend all that is precious to us. What seems so regrettable and ironic is that the casualty here is truth, specifically the historical truth, which of course is always messy and complex and hard to put into service to defend particular ideas.

Should we be optimistic or pessimistic about human nature? Well – big news! – we should be both, and that’s what history really shows us. And if we want to find ways of encouraging the best of our natures and minimizing the worst, we need to start with the here and now, and not by appeal to some imagined set of values that we have chosen to impose on history.

3 comments:

  1. Do you know the Science Fiction novel "Gallileo's Dream"? In it Gallileo has visions from a future in which residents of the Solar System conspire to change the past so that G. does not refuse his chance at martyrdom. The future descendants of earthlings believe that if G. were known to be a "real martyr" they could score some king of points in their own complicated strategy match. The vision G. has of the end the conspiracy intends for him influences him to surrender more quickly. In our own timeline it seems that Bruno has been selected for this role. Who can be certain of the motives of other, current, past, or present; or even of one' own motives?

    ReplyDelete
  2. One good thing about dictatorships is that they tend to hold power jealously, to the exclusion of government bloat. So that dictatorships, and monarchies, are potentially minimalist; as long as the dictator isn't in the lazy habit of delegation.

    Whereas a socialist utopian state, is too wonderful to be limited, and inevitably falls foul of positive feedback, and develops into intolerant despotism. Because it is wholly delegated to the 'needy', with greed cracking the whip, the people must work and die to order.

    Consider Tibet, under the monasteries, in living memory, 95% of the people were absolutely 'equal'; indeed, as 'feudal serfs' they were forbidden to be otherwise. So much for Shangri-La:

    http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Serfdom_in_Tibet_controversy

    ReplyDelete


  3. I am not concerned with the series “Cosmos” or every other’s political agenda. What I feel it is really constructive is that people want to know more about Giordano Bruno. Actually he believed in the unity of religion and science. Yet another religion of the dogmatic versions of it and another science of the blind materialistic versions of it. Matter for him was divine and Divinity material. Both transcending mere conceptualization. Check out if you care Hilary’s Gatti classics:

    http://www.amazon.com/Hilary-Gatti/e/B001HQ2JDC

    and a rare but undeservingly forgotten book by Ramon G. Mendoza:

    http://www.amazon.com/Acentric-Labyrinth-Giordano-Contemporary-Cosmology/dp/1852306408/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1395599382&sr=1-1&keywords=the+acentric+labyrinth

    More to discover if one searches why Leibniz used the term “monad” but had to conceal his sources

    http://www.amazon.com/Kabbalah-Archives-internationales-dhistoire-International/dp/0792331141/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1395599817&sr=1-1&keywords=leibniz+and+the+kabbalah

    Hope you enjoy the adventure of discovering ” … who broke those chains and those doors
    From which few rarely escape? …” :-)

    ReplyDelete

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.